|
Development Through
Wage-Led Growth
By
Henry C.K. Liu
Part
I: Stagnant
Worker Income Leads to Overcapacity
Part II: Gold
Keeps
Rising as Other Commodities Fall
Part III: Labor
Markets de-linked from the Gold Market
Part IV: Central
Banks
and Gold
Part V: Central
Banks
and Gold Liquidity
Part VI: The London
Gold Market
Part VII: Weak
Political Response to Ineffective Financial Regulation
Part VIII: Gold and
Fiat Currencies
Part IX: International
Gold
Agreements-
Historical Political Context
Part
X: The Rise and
Decline of Institutional
Economics
Part XI:
Critical Theory
This article appeared in AToL
on April 22, 2011
Institutional Economics
is a branch of Critical Theory which,
when focused on examination, analysis and
critique of society and culture, draws concepts and data from across
the entire
range of social sciences and humanities. The term Critical Theory has
two
related but different meanings with separate epistemological roots. One
meaning
of critical theory originates in sociology and the other in literary
criticism,
but the term has been use constructively in association with new
critical ways
of looking at political ideology, economic theory and even theology.
This has
led to the literal use of “critical theory” as an umbrella term to
describe any
theory founded upon critique of the unthinking intuitive, the blind
conventional or the out-dated traditional.
For example, critical theorists view the Western concept of
the rule of law in democratic political systems operating under market
capitalism as merely a method by which the ruling class, members of
which
exclusively own and/or control capital or enjoy special benefit from
the access
to and control of capital, can justify its rule over the rest of
society, as
they alone command the financial resources to determine what laws get
passed to
preserve its own narrow interest, which is to secure the perpetuation
of
capitalism and the control of capital by the ruling class to set market
conditions conducive to the maximization of return on capital as the
operating
rule of the economic system. The rule of law has become a high-sounding
cover
for attempts of the ruling class to rule by law.
Critical Theory re-evaluates
rationally the integrity and morality implied historically by the
contingent
nature of the culture that has spawned it. Critical theorists adopt
fresh hypothetical
stances against accepted traditions, and on that basis, form new
insights on cultural
relativity and hypothesis. Participants in the formation of critical
theory
take questioning stances toward commonly accepted attitudes while
nonetheless
avoiding the judgment paralysis associated with limitless moral
relativism.
The coercive application of Western ideals on non-Western societies,
such as democracy,
rule of law, individual freedom and market fundamentalism, concepts
that have
evolved in the historical and social context of the West as universal
truth make
it a legitimate target of critical theory, to expose these concepts as
components in the battle plan for a Western campaign to establish
cultural
hegemony globally. (Please see my July 11, 2003 AToL
article: The Abduction of Modernity – Part II:
That Old Time Religion).
Meta-Positivism
Modern critical
theory arose from a growth trajectory extending from meta-positivist
studies (meta – Greek word for beyond) of neutral
positivist data collection and observation to include a focus on
critical
interpretative analysis of data in the sociology of ideas - the view
that
social scientists must necessarily go beyond empiricism and scientific
methods
of analysis in the development of social theory and in the conduct of
social research,
and most importantly, the production of new concepts that have no
historical
precedent, as required by new social conditions. Meta-positivism
relates to the historical
discourse on the philosophy and sociology of social science, issues
long since
settled in natural science with the coming of the Age of Science after
physics
jumped from Newtonian mechanics to Einstein relativity.
In modern
practice, meta-positivism relies more on qualitative analysis with a
critical
view on ideology, while positivist research involves more on
quantitative
analysis to discover and understand what exists. Positivists typically
rely on
quantitative research methods such as statistical analysis, aimed at
the
identification of causality. On the other hand, meta-positivists use
research
methods that rely more on testing new theoretical hypothesis with
unstructured
interviews to collect data on market participant behavior and reaction
to
construct simulation models. With the availability of high-speed and
high-power
electronic digital computers to handle, organize and manipulate vast
amount of
quantitative data and with advances in digital behavioral modeling of
complex
economic phenomena, the gulf between quantitative digital analysis and
qualitative heuristic analog processes has been largely bridged on the
operational level.
Still, data can
only be collected and organized usefully according to particular
concepts and
theories, and theory unsubstantiated by data is mere fantasy. Without
organizing concepts or theoretical structures, data are as
uninformative as
inert masses of sand on an undisturbed beach. The most advanced
computer will
remain impotent of utility without sophisticated mission oriented
software to
turn raw unstructured input into useful purposeful output. Even rigidly
organized data can appear to different analysts armed with different
theoretical
frameworks as differently as a Rorschach test can be for different test
subjects with varying psychological constructs. The message buried in
any data
set can only be released with the subjective interpretation of the
viewer. And
different messages can be extracted by different viewers from the same
set of
data.
Milton Friedman and
Positive Economics
In economics,
positive economics focuses on understanding of existing phenomena while
normative economics focuses on creating an ideal state by changing what
is
undesirable in the existing world.
In his 1953 essay: The Methodology of Positive Economics, Milton Friedman argues against the
“basic confusion between descriptive accuracy and analytical relevance
that
underlies most criticisms of economic theory.” The
paper asserts that complex realities can be
scientifically reduced
to simple fundamental structures. And the test of this hypothesis is
its
fruits. Theory is the way through which we perceive “facts” and we
cannot
perceive “facts” without theoretical context.
Behavioral economist Andrew W. Lo, Professor and Head of
Finance at the Sloan School
at MIT, quipped in an intelligent and entertaining lecture: Warning:
Physics Envy
May Be Hazardous to
Your Wealth, to economists who envy physicists, because in physics,
3
laws explain 99% of the physical world, while in economics, 99 laws
explains
about 3% of economic phenomena.
Hume on Unobservable
Phenomena
David Hume (1711-86) pointed out in his Inquiry
into Human Understanding published in 1748 that since the
conclusion of a
valid inference could contain no information not found in the premise;
there
could be no valid conclusion from observed to unobserved phenomena.
That of
course is not to say that unobserved phenomena must be false. It's just
that
their truth cannot be validated by observable facts.
Notwithstanding denial by positive economists, economics as
a science deals mostly with unobservable facts, as observable facts are
self-evident and require no further analysis. Unobservable facts can
only be
surmised by conjecture which are subsequently tested on their validity.
For
example, unemployment is easily measured while the cause and effects of
unemployment
in the economy continues to be a matter of debate centuries after the
emergence
of the industrial market economy. Further, even the definition of
unemployment
itself is still subject to debate.
The Invisible Hand of
the Market
In neoclassical economics,
the “invisible hand of the market” is
a term used to describe the self regulating nature of free market and
market’s
tendency toward an equilibrium state. The metaphor was coined by Adam
Smith in The Theory of Moral Sentiments, to
describe the conjunction of the forces of self interest, competition
and
the law
of supply and demand, to produce the optimum allocation of resources in
a
market
economy. The concept is the founding
justification for laissez-faire
economic philosophy. The wide spread acceptance of the concept
of the
unseen hand is the coup de grace that
proves the flaw in positive economics.
The Theory of the
Invisible Hand states that if each consumer is allowed to choose freely
what to
buy and each producer is allowed to choose freely what to sell and how
to
produce it, the market will settle on a product distribution and prices
that
are beneficial to all the individual members of a community, and hence
to the
community as a whole. The concept of the invisible hand was at first
considered
a “natural inclination” in a free market, not yet a social mechanism
as it was
later classified by Leon Walras (1834-1910) and Vilfredo Pareto
(1848-1923).
Borrowing concepts
from physics, Walrus proposed the General
Equilibrium Theory as a branch of theoretical economics to
explain the
behavior of supply, demand and prices in an economy with many markets
to settle
in a general equilibrium in prices, supply and demand.
Pareto developed the
concept of Pareto Optimum, which asserts that resources are optimally
distributed
when an individual cannot move into a better position without putting
someone
else into a worse position. Much welfare economics is based on the
concept of
the Pareto Optimum. In an unjust global society, the Pareto Optimum
will
perpetuate injustice in the world.
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) emancipated man’s command of knowledge from
Humean
skepticism. In his Critique of Pure
Reason (1781), Kant emphasized the contribution of the knower to
knowledge.
An uncultured person looking at a sausage sees a delicious meal while
an art
critic would see Cubist painter Picasso. Since economists can only
collect but
not create economic data, the economist’s contribution to the science
of
economics is economic theory, without which economics will stay outside
of the
realm of discourse.
While acknowledging that the three great issues of
metaphysics - God, freedom and immortality - could not be logically
determined,
Kant asserted that their essence is a necessary presupposition. In his
subsequent publications, Critique of
Practical Reason (1788) and Critique
of Judgment (1790), Kant asserted as a moral law his famous categorical imperative, requiring moral
actions to be unconditionally and universally binding to absolute
goodwill.
Similarly, in the moral law of economics, there is a categorical
imperative
requiring moral economic actions to be unconditionally and universally
binding
to good will.
Yet goodwill is singularly absent in market fundamentalism not by
default but
by design. God and immortality appear to have been claimed by some
market
fundamentalists on the basis of their flawed logic on the issue of
freedom of
market participants to do harm to others to enhance their individual
self
interest, and that if large number of market participants are free to
do harm
to others in a free market, social good would somehow result. John
Stuart
Mill’s view on individual freedom is limited to a person’s freedom to
do only
that which does not harm others.
Positive/normative questions are distinguished by the “is/ought”
dichotomy.
John Neville Keynes, lesser known father of John Maynard Keynes,
divided
economics into “positive” (the study of “what is”, and the way the
economy
actually works), “normative” (the study of “what should be”), and the
“art of
economics” (applied economics – how to make “what should be” into “what
is”).
Intervention, be it by government or by market participants, is
inescapable for
progress.
In his essay on positive economics, Friedman tried to deny the
‘is/ought’
dichotomy by arguing that answers to ‘ought’ questions necessarily
depend on a
prior establishment of ‘what is’. Nevertheless, most critics of
Friedman’s
positive methodology feel he was arguing against normative economics
and thus
assume that he was not only arguing in favor of positive economics but
also
condoning what exists as valid.
Yet “what is” affects “what ought to be”, reflecting the
value judgment of applied economics. Thus positive methodology must
precede
normative prescriptions. But if positive methodology is used to justify
“what
is” without proceeding to “what ought to be”, then positive
investigation
becomes superfluous to human progress.
The claim of the Chicago School
that prosperity will spring from markets left free of government
interference
has been challenged by developing facts in recent decades. Recurring
financial
crises in free market economies appear to have jelled into a pattern of
10-year
cycles, as evidenced by the crashes of 1987, 1997 and 2007. By now,
after three
decades of hegemonic dominance by anti-government policy penchant and a
philosophy of unchallenged faith in the efficacy of private enterprise,
the Chicago School
theology can no longer rest
on the secure platform of political sponsorship provided by those who
directly
benefited from a rigged market disguised as manifestation of economic
freedom.
Fundamentally, it is a stretch of logic to assume that
numerous individual
market
participants each acting in strict self interest and by definition at
the
expense of the common interest (otherwise it would not be self interest
by
definition if self interest is congruent with the common interest),
would
mysteriously lead to an aggregate contribution to the common good.
The collapse of market fundamentalism as a valid theory and
the damage it has done to economies everywhere have put the Chicago
School theology
on the defensive.
Its big lie has been exposed by facts on two levels. The Chicago Boys’
claim
that helping the rich is the only way to help the poor is not only
exposed as
not true, it turns out that market fundamentalism hurts not only the
poor and
the powerless; it hurts everyone, rich and poor, albeit in different
ways.
When wages are kept low to fight inflation, the low-wage
regime causes overcapacity through over investment from excess profit.
And
monetary easing to provide liquidity under such conditions produces
hyperinflation that hurts also the rich. The fruits of Friedman’s test
are in –
and they are all rotten. Using
unemployment (zero wages) and under-employment (inadequate wages) to
fight
inflation created by central bank monetary excess (misapplied
liquidity) is a
policy of economic suicide. (Please see my September 5. 2008 AToL
article: Milton
Friedman and the Money Matters Controversy)
Critical Theory in the
Social Sciences
The social sciences
are fields that study
society through scientific methodology. The term refers to a number of
fields
outside of the natural sciences. The social sciences include:
anthropology, archaeology,
business administration, criminology, development studies, economics,
geography,
history, law, linguistics, political science, sociology, international
relations, communication, and other fields that straddle social
science,
natural science and behavioral science.
The term social
science may be used, however, in the specific context of referring to
the original science of society established in 19th century
sociology. Karl Marx
(1818-1883), Émile Durkheim (1858-1917) and Max Weber
(1864-1920) are generally
referred to as the principal architects of modern social science.
Positivism refers to a
set of epistemological perspectives and philosophies of science which
holds
that the scientific method is the most suitable approach to uncovering
the
processes by which both social events and human activities occur.
Though the
positivist approach has been a recurrent theme in the history of
Western
thought from ancient Greece to the present time, the concept was
defined in
modern terms in early 19th century by French philosopher
Auguste Comte
(1798-1857). Comte, widely recognized as a founder of the modern
sociology and
a leading framer of the modern doctrine of positivism, was strongly
influenced
by utopian socialist Henri de Saint-Simon (1760-1825) to whom Comte, 38
years
younger, served as secretary for a time when latter was a teenager.
Henri de Saint-Simon
and State-Technocratic
Socialism
Henri de
Saint-Simon advocated a form of state-technocratic socialism in which
industrialists would lead society and found a new national community
based upon
cooperation and technological progress, which would be capable of
eliminating
poverty for the masses to replace historical feudalism. Replacing the
Church as
the sole spiritual guardian for society, Siant-Simon felt the guidance
of
society should be given to men of science qualified to organize a new
society
which only productive labor is entitled to rule.
One wonders what
Saint-Simon would have to say were he confronted with Robert Louis
Stevenson’s The Strange Case of the Dr. Jekyll and Mr.
Hyde or its modern real life version in the ideological conflict
and
dishonorable personal betrayal between nuclear physicists J. Robert
Oppenheimer
and Edward Teller on the controversial question
of further post-war development of nuclear
weapons with building
hydrogen bombs, and the ignoble role Teller played in the government’s
revoke
of security clearance for Oppenheimer in the early phase of the Cold
War.
Teller’s shameful betrayal of an innocent colleague by testifying that
Oppenheimer might be a security risk led to Teller’s being ostracized
by
practically all of his colleagues in the scientific community for the
rest of
his life. Teller was widely recognized as the real-life model of
Stanley
Kubrik’s 1964 anti-war black comedy film: Dr.
Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb, based
on Peter George’s Cold War thriller novel Red Alert.
Saint-Simon did
not address the issue of the adversarial relationship between
management and
labor in the modern industrial economy, since he viewed productive
labor
as the
rightful ruler of a non-exploitative socialist order constructed by men
of
science. In such a socialist society, confrontation between labor and
management would be structurally nonexistent.
Saint-Simon was
so impressed by the absence of hereditary
aristocratic titles and social privileges he saw in the US in its early
society
that he renounced his own aristocratic title in Europe and came to
favor a form
of scientific meritocracy for organizing society, becoming convinced
that
modern science was the key to progress and that it would be possible to
develop
a society based on objective scientific principles. As the global
economy
developed, except for a brief period when the likes of Thomas Edison
and
Alexander Bell were financially successful inventors, scientists and
engineers would come to be dominated by manipulators of capital to
serve the
principle of maximum return on capital.
Saint-Simon’s
early publications, such as his Introduction aux travaux
scientifiques du
XIXe siècle (Introduction to scientific discoveries of the 19th
century)
(1803) and his Mémoire sur la science de l'homme (Notes on
the Science of
Mankind) (1813), being a eulogy to the policies of Napoleon in
support of
science, demonstrate his (Saint-Simon’s) faith in science as a means to
regenerate society.
Saint-Simon
envisioned the present-day European Union in his 1814 essay De la
réorganisation de la société européenne (On
the Reorganization of European
Society), written in collaboration with his then secretary,
historian Augustin
Thierry, who enthusiastically embraced the socio-political ideals of
the French
Revolution and Saint-Simon’s vision of an ideal future society.
However,
Saint-Simon expected Britain to be the lead in forming a continent
sharing the
same laws and institutions. As it turned out, British legal and
institutional
mismatch with Napoleonic Continental Europe emerged as the main obstacle in Britain’s joining the EU.
As a scientific
thinker, Saint-Simon ironically and unscientifically relied on
anecdotal
evidence to support his findings, without developing a systematic
theory. For
example, he seemed to be unaware or unconcerned that feudalism, which
he
criticised as a non-merit-based hierarchical social system, was
initially
organized as a form of meritocracy. The aristocracy was initially made
up of
men of distinction, mostly warriors, on whom nobility status was
conferred by
the recognizing royal authority on behalf of feudal society. It was the
attempt
of meritorious individuals to perpetuate the earned privilege society
granted
to them by passing on the earned privilege to their offspring without
their
offspring having to earn it that led to the rise of hereditary
feudalism.
Saint-Simon did
not deal insightfully with the problem of how to prevent the natural
social
evolution from meritocracy to heritocracy as a new form of intellectual
and
economic feudalism in the modern scientific capitalist order. Yet
Saint-Simon
exerted great influence on modern thought, as the founder of French
socialism,
which influenced the thinking of Karl Marx, 58 years younger, and as a
seeding
for much of Auguste Comte’s theory of industrial progress, which in
turn
influenced Émile Durkheim who was forty years younger than Marx.
Auguste Comte and
Positive Philosophy
Comte (1798-1857)
developed his positive philosophy out of personal experience of
the
irrational social chaos during the French Revolution (1787-1799). He
was born nine years after the Storming of the Bastille which took place on July 14, 1789, marking the beginning
of the
French Revolution .
Comte as a
philosopher sought a new social paradigm via rational scientific
methods. As
with Saint-Simon, Comte also exerted considerable influence in 19th
century thought and socio-political economy discourse, influencing such
intellectual giants as John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), eight years
younger than
Comte, and later, Karl Marx, born 12 year later than
Mill. Comte’s version of sociologie and
his notion of social
evolutionism set the tone for pioneering social theorists and
anthropologists
such as Harriet Martineau (1802-1876) and later, Herbert Spencer
(1820-1903).
Modern academic sociology was later formally established in the 1890s
by Émile
Durkheim (1858-1917) in his thirties, with a firm emphasis on objective
social
research.
Antinomy in Economics
The term antinomy (in Greek: αντι - meaning
against, νομος
-meaning law) literally means the mutual incompatibility, real or
apparent,
of two laws. It is a term used in logic and epistemology, the branch of
philosophy
concerned with the nature and limitations of knowledge. The term
acquired special
significance in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who used
the term antinomy to describe equally rational
processes
that lead to contradictory conclusions, such as applying to pure
thought the criteria
of reason that is proper only to sensual perception or experience (phenomena). Empirical reason cannot play
a causal role in establishing rational truth because rational truth
goes beyond
the realm of sensual experience; and because to do so would be applying
empirical reasoning to the sphere of rational truth, a level that
transcends empirical
reasoning.
The concept of antinomy
was part of Kant’s critical
program of determining limits to science and philosophical inquiry,
when a
thesis contradicts an antithesis. These contradictions are inherent in
reason
when it is applied to the world as it exists, independently of one’s
perceptions of it. Kant’s saw these contradiction as the distinction
between phenomena (from Greek φαινόμενoν
- observable occurrence by the physical senses) and noumena
(from Greek νοούμενoν,
present participle of νοέω - “I
think”, to describe that which is known without involving the physical
senses.
Noumena, a Greek word, is similar to the Latin word cogito, which was used in Cogito
ergo sum (I think, therefore I am) by René Descartes (1596-1650), a key figure of the Enlightenment who preceded
Kant by 128 years. The famous phrase: Cogito ergo sum
was used by Descartes in his Discourse on the Method
of
Rightly Conducting One's Reason and of Seeking Truth in the Sciences
(French title: Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa
raison, et
chercher la vérité dans les sciences), published in
1637.
Kant’s goal in
his critical philosophy was to set limits beyond which claims could not
be
justified, and antinomy was a
particularly illustrative example of his larger philosophical inquiry.
Survival of the
Fittest as a Social Myth
Herbert Spencer
coined the phrase “survival of the fittest” in a socio-economic context
in
1864, six decades after Kant’s death, reportedly after reading Charles
Darwin's On the
Origin of Species, published in 1859.
From Darwin’s scientific law on
natural selection, Spencer push the
edge of the envelope beyond
biological evolutionary phenomenon in its original context of the
natural
environment. Spencer’s claim of the validity of “the survival of the
fittest”
in a socio-economic context is a classic case of antinomy.
Unlike the natural environment which is not subject to
fundamental restructuring by animals that are born into it, and
therfore must
adjust to it, the human social environment is an artificial construct
created
by men who have the ability to modify it as humanity evolves towards
higher
social purposes. Mankind has the intelligence and power to create and
modify
his social environment to nurture the fittest survivors in an ideal
image, and
not let a diseased social environment dictate a malignant evolutionary
destiny
on mankind. It is a struggle symbolized by the conflict between Spartan
and
Athens, by the conflict between Carlyle and Spencer.
After the Revolutions
of 1848 and political agitation in the United Kingdom, Carlyle
published a
collection of essays entitled "Latter-Day Pamphlets" (1850) in which
he attacked democracy as an absurd social ideal, while equally
condemning
hereditary aristocratic leadership in favor of heroic meritocracy.
Spencer’s theory
of “cosmic evolution”, expounded in his Principles
of Biology (1864), involves the scientific study of universal
change. While
cosmic evolution attempts to integrate within social science other
scientific
theories such as biological evolution, it is not itself a theory or a
product
of reproducible evidence that leads to acceptance by the scientific
community.
Spencer connected
the biological findings of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744-1829) that an organism could pass on
to its offspring
physical traits that it acquired to enhance its survivability during
its life
span, with the positive philosophy of Auguste Comte, who had proposed a
theory
of socio-cultural evolution that society progresses by a general Law of
Three Stages,
which states that society as a whole, and each particular science,
develops
through three mentally conceived stages: (1) the theocratic stage, (2)
the metaphysical
stage, and (3) the positive stage. The Positivity stage refers to
scientific
explanation based on observation, experiment, and comparison. Positive
explanations rely upon a distinct scientific method, for its
justification.
Socio-cultural
evolution is the process
by which structural reorganization of society is affected through the
passage
of time, eventually producing a social form or structure which is
qualitatively
different from the ancestral social form shaped by a primitive man less
able to
control his environment. Spencer saw human progress as being propelled
by
primeval savage competitive human traits reinforced by technology and
sanitized
by rituals, rather than an evolution of a higher harmonious form of
humanity
conditioned by love and charity. To this regressive evolution of
humanity,
Spencer added the concepts of natural selection borrowed from
zoological
evolution as spelled out in Darwin’s influential 1859 book On the
Origin of
Species.
To Darwin,
natural selection, a key mechanism of biological evolution, is the
process by
which desirable physical traits in living species become more common in
a population,
due to consistent effects from the reproductive survival of the bearers
of such
traits. The natural genetic variation within a population of organisms
may
cause some individuals to survive and reproduce more successfully than
others
in their contemporary environment. Natural selection is not connected
to issues
of morality, only to probability of survival in a hostile environment.
If the
environment requires aggressiveness as a prerequisite for survival,
natural
selection will create a race of aggressors.
To Darwin,
species that evolve in harsh environments such as the desert, or the
icy polar
region, will produce species that would be more fit for such
environments
rather than gentle lamb on a peaceful perrie. Darwin was merely
recording an
observation, without moral preference. Evolution is a biological
process, not a
moral choice or value judgment for Darwin who saw every specie having
a place
in the sun and in the food chain as a fact of nature. Darwin certainly
never
advocated that human society should ape the natural environment. The
entire
history of human civilization involves human intervention on the
natural to
retain the good and to shed the bad.
One of the most
important contribution made by science to human progress is the
advancement of
precise pharmaceutical counteraction to illnesses found in the natural
environment, such as those caused by harmful bacteria. Medical
intervention
enable mankind to defy the law of the survival of the fittest by
allowing the
less fit to survive with the help of medicine and education. An analogy
can be
made between public health and socio-economic well being to show the
preference
for government non-intervention in a market economy as unjustifiable in
terms
of facilitating proper metabolism of human progress.
The Voodoo Science of
Social Darwinism
Others who came
after Darwin began to apply Darwin’s observation of nature as a natural
philosophy for organizing human society under the banner of Social
Darwinism,
with an implied judgment that whatever survives is the outcome of
progress and
is above moral concerns. Survival of the fittest in a competitive
social
environment will eventually turn human society into a harsh and
dangerous hell
rather than a Garden of Eden. Survival of the fittest, as a human
evolutionary
process, will justify an escalating circular feedback loop of mutually
reinforcement between increasingly more aggressive species and
environments
that increasingly require more aggressiveness for survival.
Darwin observed
that natural selection acts on the phenotype, the observable
characteristics of
an organism, but the heritable genetic basis of any phenotype which
gives a
reproductive advantage will become more common in a population, a
process known
as allele frequency, which is
the proportion of all copies
of a gene that is made up of a particular gene variant allele,
one of two or more forms of the DNA sequence of a
particular gene. Each gene can have different alleles.
Sometimes, different DNA sequences (alleles) can result
in different physical traits, such as color and
size, or non-physical trait such as intelligence and affinity. Other
times,
different alleles will have the same
result in the expression of a gene.
Over time, this
process can lead to adaptations by specialized populations for
particular ecological
niches and may even eventually result in the emergence of new species.
In other
words, natural selection is an important, though not exclusive process
by which
evolution takes place within a population of organism in an environment
beyond
the control of the specie.
Human Society and
Natural Environment
As opposed to
social selection, in which human societies favor and reinforce certain
specific
social traits over anti-social traits in the population through the
social
institution of marriage and other ritualistic institutions, in natural
selection, the environment acts as a disinterested sieve through which
only
certain variations appropriate to environmental conditions can pass to
fit into
the environment. It is a process of surrendering the natural traits of
a specie
to the requirement of an unyieldingly rigid and hostile environment.
But unlike the
natural environment, the social environment is created by man, and it
can be
designed to enhance man’s ideal existence. In a social environment that
rewards
aggression and greed, as societies that adopt capitalist markets do,
aggressively greedy individuals will be the fittest to survive. Most
religions,
with the exception of Calvinism, try to influence the social milieu to
be less
aggressive and greedy, by encouraging the image of God as loving and
charitable.
Calvinism and
Capitalism
Calvinism has
been identified by social historians as the driving force behind the
rise of modern
capitalism in a revolt against the medieval condemnation of usury and,
implicitly, of unearned or passive profit.
Richard Henry Tawney (1880
– 1962), English Christian socialist, economic historian and social
critic,
wrote Religion and the Rise of Capitalism (1926), in which he
explored
the causal relationship between Protestantism and economic development
in the
16th and 17th centuries. Tawney “bemoaned the
division
between commerce and social morality brought about by the Protestant
Reformation, leading as it did to the subordination of Christian
teaching to
the pursuit of material wealth.” Tawney took up Max Weber’s thesis on
the
causal connection between the appearance of Protestantism and the rise
of
capitalism. Weber’s book: The
Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism,
appeared in German in 1904-05, and
was translated into English for the first time by Harvard sociologist
Talcott
Parsons only in 1930, four years after the publication of Tawney book
on the
same subject.
Spencer’s
Rationalization of Social Evolution
Spencer wrote that
over time societies will progress, presumably towards Spencer’s vision
of a
higher state of civilization, and that human progress is accomplished
through
industrious competition. He defined progress narrowly as advancement of
survival skills in a man-made socio-economic order, through technology
and
socio-political organization that will reward such skills, leaving
unexplored
the possibility that amoral technological skills could overwhelm the
advancement of humanity to allow the malignant growth of cancerous
agents that
would metastasize the human spirit.
Spencer ignored
factual evidence in history by labeling early human societies that
survived
through in-group cooperation and symbiotic co-existence with other
species, and
with the natural environment, as a “primitive” state, ignoring the fact
that
humanity as a whole has repeatedly enhanced its own survivability
through
cooperative arrangements among different human sub-groups and
societies.
Spencer stressed
the role of the self-centered individual acting narrowly in his self
interest,
rather than the harmonious collective, as the unit of analysis (the
basic entity
in the analysis of social studies) in social evolution. Social
evolution
through natural and social selection affects social as well as
biological
phenomena. The antinomy in the concept of individualist “survival of
the
fittest” in human society is that it can lead to the survival of the
most
socially unfit human beings and the evolution of increasing vile
ecosystems
that would eventually wipe out all that is good and graceful in
humanity.
Scientific Darwinism
Distorted as Political
Philosophy
The publication
of Darwin’s influential book: On the Origin of Species in 1859
unintendedly gave a holy bible to proponents of the controversial idea
that
socio-cultural evolution of human society is a process of survival of
the
fittest in the context of capitalist market fundamentalism. The idea of
biological evolution of survival of the fittest in a hostile natural
environment beyond the control of the biological inhabitants has been
commandeered as convenient justification for the development of
capitalistic
market society for human beings whose natural traits are not naturally
in sync
with that society's requirements for survival.
The implication
of the acceptance of the laws of nature as a destiny rather than a tool
of
progress is that whatever survives in nature is considered as morally
valid and
good, rather than whatever is good and moral should survive in
civilized
society constructed by man of vision. Human civilization under the law
of
survival of the fittest competitive market capitalism will evolve away
from
that which is morally good and socially desirable in human beings
because such
human traits are often the most fragile and unfit for survival in a
society
where ethics is not only perceived as weakness, but is actually a
impediment to
survival.
The revolutionary
power of Mao Zedong rests not only on his political organizing skill,
but on
his unflinching belief that the oppressed, the poor, the
underprivileged, the
uncultured, the uneducated and the powerless, in other words, the
socio-economically unfit, have an innate goodness and the invincible
power to
change society toward higher stages of civilization where oppression,
poverty,
inequality and ignorance will be vestiges of the uncivilized past
because this
group can be expected not to resist reform and revolution for they have
little
to protect or to lose. Marx places his faith in oppressed workers as
the
revolutionary force because they have “nothing to lose but heir chains”.
Kropotkin and
Anarchism
Using cooperative
symbiotic behavior found in animals as a model for organizing human
society,
Russian zoologist, evolutionary theorist and anarchist Peter Kropotkin
(1842-1921), despite his privileged position as a hereditary prince in
Czarist
Russia, advocated a communist society free of private ownership and
free from governmental
authority, based on voluntary associations between productive citizens
as
outlined in his 1902 book, Mutual
Aid: A Factor of Evolution.
In Freedom
Pamphlets No. 1. (New Edition. 1920.) The
Wage system, Kroputkin wrote:
“In their plan
for the
reconstruction of society, the Collectivists commit, in our opinion, a
double
error. Whilst speaking of the abolition of the rule of capital, they
wish,
nevertheless, to maintain two institutions which form the very basis of
that
rule, namely, representative government and the wage system.”
Kroputkin saw representative government as a system designed
by the bourgeoisie to replace monarchism while maintaining and
augmenting capitalist
domination over workers. As people become conscious of their suppressed
economic interests and latent political power, and as the variety of
such
interests expands, the capitalist political system becomes inoperative.
Kroputkin
asserted that the wage system should be abolished along with private
property in
favor of possession in common of the instruments of production.
Proudhon: Property is
Theft!
Thirty-three years before
Kropotkin, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
(1809-1865), French mutualist philosopher
and socialist member of the French Parliament, was reportedly the first
philosopher to proudly wear the label “anarchist”. After the
Revolutions of 1848,
Proudhon began to call himself a federalist.
Proudhon’s
best-known assertion is that Property is Theft!, contained in
his first
major work, What is Property? Or, an Inquiry into the Principle of
Right and
Government (Qu'est-ce que la propriété? Recherche
sur le principe du
droit et du gouvernement), published in 1840. The book’s
publication
attracted the hostile attention of the French authorities. It also
attracted
the sympathetic scrutiny of Marx, who started a correspondence with its
author.
Proudhon and Marx
influenced each other: they met in Paris while Marx was exiled there.
Their
friendship finally ended when Marx responded to Proudhon's The
System of
Economic Contradictions, or The Philosophy of Poverty with the
provocatively titled The Poverty of Philosophy. The dispute
became one
of the sources of the ideological split between the anarchist and
Marxist wings
of the International Working Men's Association.
Proudhon favored
workers associations or co-operatives, as well as individual
worker/peasant
possession, over private ownership or the nationalization of land and
workplaces. He considered that social revolution could be achieved in a
peaceful manner. In The Confessions of a Revolutionary Proudhon
asserted
that, Anarchy is Order, the phrase which much later inspired,
in the
view of some, the anarchist circled-A symbol, today “one of the
most
common graffiti on the urban landscape.” He unsuccessfully tried to
create a national
bank, to be funded by what became an abortive attempt at an income tax
on capitalists
and stockholders. Similar in some respects to a credit union, it would
have
given interest-free loans.
Proudhon
published his own perspective for reform which was completed in 1849, Solution
du problème social (Solution of the
Social Problem), in which he laid out a program of mutual financial
cooperation among workers to transfer control of the economy from
capitalists
and financiers to workers. The central part of his plan was the
establishment
of a bank to provide low interest rate credit with the issuing exchange
notes
to replace money based on gold.
Proudhon ran for
the constituent assembly in April 1848, but was not elected. He was
successful,
in the complementary elections of June 4, and served as a deputy during
the
debates over the National Workshops, created by the February 25, 1848,
decree
passed by Republican Louis Blanc. The Workshops were to give work to
the
unemployed. Proudhon was never enthusiastic about such Workshops,
perceiving
them to be essentially charitable institutions that did not resolve the
unemployment problem of the economic system. But he was against their
elimination unless an alternative could be found for the workers who
relied on
the Workshops for subsistence.
As a consequence
of his opposition to profit, wage labor, worker exploitation, ownership
of land
and capital, as well as to state property, Proudhon rejected both
capitalism
and communism. He adopted the term mutualism for his brand of
anarchism, which
involved control of the means of production by the workers. Proudhon
opposed
the charging of interest and rent, but did not seek to abolish them by
law.
Proudhon was a
revolutionary, but his revolution did not mean violent upheaval or
civil war,
but rather the transformation of society. This transformation was
essentially
moral in nature and demanded the highest ethics from those who sought
change.
It was monetary reform, combined with organizing a credit bank and
workers
associations, that Proudhon proposed to use as a lever to bring about
the
organization of society along new lines. He did not suggest how the
monetary
institutions would cope with the problem of inflation and with the need
for the
efficient and equitable allocation of scarce resources.
Mutualism
Co-evolution of
mutualistic systems in nature have been thoroughly studied, such as he
interdependence between the swollen-thron acacias and their ant
inhabitants. In
this species pair, the ant is dependent on acacdia for food and
domicile, and
the acadia is dependent on the ant for protection from phytophagous
insects and
neighboring plants.
Post-Cold War
international relations are built on the principle of interdependence
of
independent sovereign states. Emerging in 1815 from a generation of
Napoleonic
wars, Europe went through a period of spectacular material progress.
The
post-war European economy had to adjust to the sudden end of war
production,
and to market readjustment from the collapse of Napoeon’s Continental
System,
to repayment of enormous war debts and to war inflation. The task of
post-war
reconstruction was easier because, unlike the two world wars, the
Napoleonic
wars did little collateral damage to European cities and farming
villages due
to the fact that much of the fighting had taken place on open battle
fields,
and the Clauswitzian concept of demolishing the will of the enemy
population to
resist has not taken root fully until WWII.
But the most
important cause for the Europan ascendance was the Industrial
Revolution, which
began first in Britain, that changed the lives of people and
traditional
socio-economic relationships in society that created new diametrically
opposite
conflicts between two new classes the had emerged in society in the
form of
capitalists and the proletariat. On the one hand, the socio-economic
forces of
industrialization brought about the rise of capitalism to check
reactionary
attempts to reverse the socio-political consequences of the French
Revolution
back to the ancien régime. On the
other, it ushered in the rise of Western Europe in the Age of
Imperialism.
The Rise of Industrial
Economy
Before 1800,
wealth in the European economy was largely trapped in land that was
relatively
evenly owned by a large number of small farmers. These small land
owners had
little incentive to risk their wealth through investment in new
ventures. The
setting up of a concentration of machine production in factories
required major
shift in land use as well as mass relocation of population from rural
areas to
cities that resulted in a broad reorganization of the ownership of the
means of
production and distribution of the resultant wealth.
The Glorious
Revolution of 1688 in England confirmed the political ascendance of a
class of
large land owners allied with a capitalist class of merchants and
financiers
concentrated in London. The Industrial Revolution was the sparked by a
sudden
burst of applied science and technology in the 1800s that enabled the
invention
of machines powered by combustion fuels to produce an economy which
required
intensive and massive use of capital to enhance the productivity of
industrial
workers. Early industrialization took hold first in textile
manufacturing.
England’s wealth from the Agricultural Revolution gave her the ability
to
finance industrial development that faced higher risk than farming and
that
required a long-time frame before profit could be forthcoming.
This
transformation of the economic order from agriculture to industry was
the
economic consequence of the political order that emerged after the
Glorious
Revolution, with Parliament captured by a few large land owners who
introduced
and passed new legislation in the form of “enclosure acts” to suspend
the
ancient common rights of open fields in rural villages based on Common
Law.
Ownership of land fell into the hands of a small class of the large
land owners
to rented land to tenant farmers. This resulted in increased farm
production
with fewer farm workers, and the release of surplus labor for newly
established
industrial enterprises and for war. This socio-economic order reach its
height
of development after the Napoleonic wars.
The dark side of
the Industrial Revolution in England was the rise of urban slums
vividly
described by Charles Dickens in his novels of social realism and by
Oliver
Goldsmith in The Deserted Village:
Ill
fares the land, to hastening ills a prey,
Where
wealth accumulates, and men dcay:
Prices
and lords may flourish, or may fade
A
breath can make them, as a breath has made;
But
a bold peasantry, their country's pride,
When once destroyed, can never be supplied.
English yeomanry
(samll land owners), the bold peasantry,
disappeared as a class to become wage laborers for large land owner,
merchants
and later for factory owners. Low wages prevented the full development
of a
domestic market and the gap was filled by international trade in search
of
foreign markets were luxury imports were bought by the local financial
elite
overseas and later low-price manufacturing goods were bought by the
general
consumers.
The Agricultural
Revolution in England caused a population explosion, with Great Britain
and
Ireland tripling in population between 1750 and 1850, rising from 10
million to
30 million. In 1785, there were only three cities with more than 30,000
people.
By 1855, seven decade later, there were 31 cities of that size.
The Manchester School
on Free Trade
Manchester was
the pre-eminent new city in the Industrial Revolution, focusing mainly
on
textile manufacturing for export since the domestic market was
under-developed
due to insufficient purchasing power as a result of low wages. The rise
of
international trade was fueled directly from the economic effects of
low
local
wages. Thus rose the Manchester School of economics of international
free
trade.
Manchester was
the hub of the world’s textile manufacturing industry, and had a high
portion of
its population earning its livelihood as factory workers, who were
disadvantaged by the Corn Laws, the protectionist policy that imposed
tariffs
on imported wheat that kept the price of food high. The Corn Laws were
supported by the land-owning aristocracy, because by reducing foreign
competition through tariffs, landowners could keep grain prices high
and
therefore, as the population expanded, increase agricultural profits
denominated in local currency.
However, the
operation of the Corn Laws also meant that the factory workers in the
textile
mills in the textile cities of northern England were faced with higher
food
bills; consequently the mill owners in turn suffered higher wage bills
and
therefore higher prices for finished-goods which restricted their
competitiveness in foreign trade denominated in gold.
Manchester became
the headquarters of the Anti-Corn Law League from 1839. The League
campaigned
against the Corn Laws to reduce food prices by allowing low price food
imports
and increases the competitiveness of English manufactured goods abroad.
Manchester Trade Liberalism grew out of this economic order. Manchester
capitalism, based on mercantilism, challenged the existing agricultural
economic order in 16th–18th century Europe.
Mercantilism
holds that a country’s prosperity is dependent on surplus trade through
exports
denominated in gold while limited free imports to raw material and
food. At the
beginning of the 19th century, trade in Britain was still subject to
import
quotas, price ceilings and other state interventions. This led to
shortages of
certain goods and, in particular, corn and wheat on British markets as
the
economy shifted by argicultural to industrial production.
The Manchester
Trade Liberals argued that free trade would lead to a more equitable
society,
making essential products available to all. Theoretically, Manchester
Trade
Liberalism was founded on the economics writings of David Hume, Adam
Smith and Jean-Baptiste
Say. (Please see my May 1, 2002 AToL article : Big Money and Corn Laws)
Britain enjoyed a
monopoly in textile manufacturing and machine tools production
unchallenged in
international trade until 1870. Equally importantly, London became the
center of
world finance and insurance to facilitate the rapid rise of
international
trade. England was the first FIRE (finance, insurance and real estate)
economy. The FIRE Economy operates
by extracting economic rents, such as interest on debt and asset price
appreciation from the production side of the economy in amounts that
exceed the
value of productivity. The FIRE economy
is a malignant
form of market capitalism.
The term
“capitalism” did not appear in the English speaking world until 1854,
while the
term communism was used in German by Karl Marx in 1848.
According to the Oxford
English Dictionary (OED), the term capitalism was first
used by
novelist William Makepeace Thackeray in 1854 in The Newcomes,
where he
meant "having ownership of capital”. Also
according to the OED, Carl Adolph Douai,
a German-American socialist and abolitionist, used the term private
capitalism in 1863.
April 18, 2011
Next: The Failed
Revolutions of 1848 - Economic Background
|
|